Stephen Jay Gould Panda Thumb Pdf Printer

 admin  

Citation: Swartz BA (2009) On the “Duel” Nature of History: Revisiting Contingency versus Determinism. PLoS Biol 7(12): e1000259. Published: December 15, 2009 Copyright: © 2009 Brian Andrew Swartz. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited. Funding: No specific funding was received for this article. Competing interests: The author has declared that no competing interests exist. “Organisms are not billiard balls, propelled by simple and measurable external forces to predictable new positions on life's pool table.

  1. Ncse

Sufficiently complex systems have greater richness. Organisms have a history that constrains their future in myriad, subtle ways.”—Stephen Jay Gould (1980: 16) What is the relationship between external—physical and biological—influences on increasingly complex matter over billions of years?

Stephen jay gould panda thumb pdf printer driver

In his most recent book, Islands in the Cosmos: the Evolution of Life on Land, Dale Russell attempts to answer this question. Russell is the senior curator of paleontology at the North Carolina Museum of Natural Sciences and, among other things, is well known for proposing in 1971 an extraterrestrial cause for the Cretaceous-Tertiary extinction that wiped out the non-avian dinosaurs. This places Russell among the first paleontologists to consider this extinction as a relatively sudden event in Earth's history. Dale Russell has spent his lifetime pondering grand evolutionary questions, and it is a quest that Islands in the Cosmos well illustrates.

His central thesis explains that evolutionary theory (as he views it)—based on “random mutations” and “adaptation to irregular changes in the physical environment”—inadequately accounts for long-term trends in the competitive abilities of organisms and the ultimate appearance of sentient beings (e.g., Homo sapiens) in the cosmos. Russell instead proposes that even though mutations are random, because “the effects of natural selection are not random, and modulated by adaptive responses to irregular changes in the physical environment,” properties of matter and feedback in biotic competition have established a deterministic trajectory in the history of life.

His argument distills to the following interrelated points:. The universe is fine-tuned for life as we know it. The physical workings of the Earth (e.g., its radius and tilt, mantle convection, the heterogeneity of continental surfaces, and a long-term stable environment) favor the origin of life and evolution of multicellular terrestrial beings.

Positive feedback and competitive interactions among organisms increase evolutionary rates, competitive abilities, activity levels, and behavioral complexity of these beings over time. Convergent evolution is a testament to these precepts, and sentient beings are a natural and emergent outcome of these processes.

Although he broadly frames these issues in the introductory pages and synthesizes them in the final chapter, Russell dedicates the bulk of this self-proclaimed essay to a chronology of evolution in the broad sense, as “change through time”. In 289 pages (82% of the book), Russell retells the 13.7 Ga (billion year) history of our cosmos and the ∼3.8–3.5 Ga history of life on Earth.

He provides occasional “hints” of his thesis in the larger chapter text and briefly elaborates on them in the final paragraphs of each chapter, but for the most part, his main ideas seem to get lost in the bombardment of historical and paleoecological facts through time. His love of dinosaurs and of the Cretaceous Period certainly shines through the wash of information.

For example, when framing the seven most important scientific debates over the last 50 years, three of the seven questions include controversy over dinosaurian evolution. Unfortunately, however, in an attempt to pull information from such a broad range of disciplines, there are several mistakes and irregularities that the specialist might find distracting. For example, instead of explaining that structures and sequences (as opposed to whole organisms) are recapitulated during ontogeny, Russell incorrectly argues that we replay “the previous evolutionary history of our ancestors” (pg. Russell's synopsis of the cosmos, the Earth, and life through time might otherwise interest the triviaphile, but it is difficult to know his intended audience. Specialized terms are often used without explanation (e.g., Opiliones, an obscure group of arachnids), and basic concepts are commonly followed with reasonable elaboration (e.g., natural selection). Irrespective of his intent to commit much of his essay to the historical record (i.e., so that if rejected, his thesis “will not detract from an appreciation of the history of terrestrial life on our planet” pg.

319), his ideas nonetheless touch upon several important evolutionary questions. Russell's central question is whether evolution is “random (contingent) or directional (teleological)” (pg. Although he passionately argues for ultimate direction (i.e., determinism) and promotes the view of being “inevitably human in a lonely universe”, he never fully explains what contingency means (it is simply when preexisting events determine the nature of succeeding ones), or relates his thesis to essential evolutionary notions that naturally emerge from these “ultimate” evolutionary questions. Thus, to understand his thesis more fully, it is necessary to explain a few additional evolutionary details. Russell's major biological precepts derive from the modern synthesis—the intellectual fusion of Darwin's concept of natural selection with Mendel's “heritable factors,” or genes —and he clearly subscribes to the view that variation is copious and non-directional, that natural selection as an external driver acts at the level of organisms to impose direction, that organismal competition promotes divergence (like Darwin's “principle of divergence” ), and that the full panoply of life's diversity arises when these tenets are extended (i.e., extrapolated) over geologic time. Although his addition to these precepts includes the argument that physical and biological influences impose ultimate direction on life's trajectory, his thesis is fundamentally founded in the dogma of the modern synthesis. Thus, by ignoring and/or rejecting the historiographic account of evolutionary ideas over the last 150 years, Russell has come to argue that macroevolutionary direction derives from the role of external influences and extrapolationist thinking.

In other words, in his view, external factors impose a deterministic outcome on the history of life. References. 1. J (1980) The panda's thumb: more reflections on natural history. New York: W.W. Norton Company, Inc. Gould1980The panda's thumb: more reflections on natural historyNew YorkW.W.

Stephen Jay Gould Panda Thumb Pdf Printer

Norton Company, Inc.343. 2.

Russell D, Tucker W (1971) Supernovae and the extinction of the dinosaurs. Nature 229: 553–554.D. Tucker1971Supernovae and the extinction of the dinosaurs.Nature229553554. 3. J (1977) Ontogeny and phylogeny. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Gould1977Ontogeny and phylogenyCambridgeHarvard University Press.501.

Serial number for borderlands goty The method suggested is to use a 360-degree protractor with the 0 division at North. I find that people who use Radiesthesia for the selection of soil, etc., pay particular attention to the fundamental rays of the substances they have under test. If both rays are nearly the same, excellent results may be expected, but if they are more than 90 apart the soil and plant are incompatible.

4. Conway Morris S (2003) Life's solution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Conway Morris2003Life's solutionCambridgeCambridge University Press.431. 5. Mayer E (1963) Animal species and evolution. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Mayer1963Animal species and evolutionCambridgeHarvard University Press.797. 6. Darwin C (1859) On the origin of species by means of natural selection, or preservation of favored races in the struggle for life. London: Murray. Darwin1859On the origin of species by means of natural selection, or preservation of favored races in the struggle for lifeLondonMurray.513.

Panda

7. J (2002) The structure of evolutionary theory. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Gould2002The structure of evolutionary theoryCambridgeHarvard University Press.1433. 8. Galton F (1869) Hereditary genius. London: MacMillian.

Galton1869Hereditary geniusLondonMacMillian.414. 9. P (1988) The influence of variation and developmental constraints on the rate of multivariate phenotypic evolution. J Evol Biol 1: 45–66.G.

Wagner1988The influence of variation and developmental constraints on the rate of multivariate phenotypic evolution.J Evol Biol14566. 10. J (1989) A developmental constraint in Cerion, with comments on the definition and interpretation of constraint in evolution. Evolution 43: 516–539.S. Gould1989A developmental constraint in Cerion, with comments on the definition and interpretation of constraint in evolution.Evolution43516539. 11. J (1982) Darwinism and the expansion of evolutionary theory.

Science 216: 380–387.S. Gould1982Darwinism and the expansion of evolutionary theory.Science216380387. 12. J, Eldridge N (1977) Punctuated equilibria: the tempo and mode of evolution reconsidered.

Paleobiology 3: 115–151.S. Eldridge1977Punctuated equilibria: the tempo and mode of evolution reconsidered.Paleobiology3115151. 13. M (1975) A theory of evolution above the species level. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A 72: 646–650.S. Stanley1975A theory of evolution above the species level.Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A72646650.

14. S (1980) Evolution, species, and fossils: how does life evolve? S Afr J Sci 76: 61–84.E. Vrba1980Evolution, species, and fossils: how does life evolve?S Afr J Sci766184. 15. A (1995) Hierarchical approaches to macroevolution: recent work on species selection and the “effect hypothesis.” Annu Rev Ecol Syst 26: 301–321.T.

Grantham1995Hierarchical approaches to macroevolution: recent work on species selection and the “effect hypothesis.”Annu Rev Ecol Syst26301321. 16. S (1989) Levels of selection and sorting with special reference to the species level. Oxford Surveys Evol Biol 6: 111–168.E. Vrba1989Levels of selection and sorting with special reference to the species level.Oxford Surveys Evol Biol6111168.

Ncse

17. J (1986) The hierarchical expansion of sorting and selection: Sorting and selection cannot be equated.

Paleobiology 12: 217–228.E. Gould1986The hierarchical expansion of sorting and selection: Sorting and selection cannot be equated.Paleobiology12217228. 18. Seilacher A (1970) Arbeitskonzept zur Konstruktionsmorphologie. Lethaia 3: 393–396.A.

Seilacher1970Arbeitskonzept zur Konstruktionsmorphologie.Lethaia3393396. 19. L (1999) Heterochrony: beyond worlds.

Paleobiology 25: 149–153.M. McKinney1999Heterochrony: beyond worlds.Paleobiology25149153. 20. S, Eldridge N (1984) Individuals, hierarchies, and processes: toward a more complete evolutionary theory. Paleobiology 10: 146–171.E. Eldridge1984Individuals, hierarchies, and processes: toward a more complete evolutionary theory.Paleobiology10146171. 21.

B, McPhail J. D (2000) Historical contingency and ecological determinism interact to prime speciation in sticklebacks, Gasterosteus. Proc R Soc Lond B 267: 2375–2384.E. McPhail2000Historical contingency and ecological determinism interact to prime speciation in sticklebacks, Gasterosteus.Proc R Soc Lond B4.

22. Manson N, editor.

(2003) God and design: the teleological argument and modern Science. London: Routledge. Manson2003God and design: the teleological argument and modern ScienceLondonRoutledge.400.

23. J (2006) Historical contingency and the purported uniqueness of evolutionary innovations. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A 103: 1804–1809.G. Vermeij2006Historical contingency and the purported uniqueness of evolutionary innovations.Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A9.

   Coments are closed